Monday, December 8, 2008

CLifford's Argument

Those of you who clicked the link on my last post were treated (or subjected, depending on your perspective) to a famous article by William Kingdom Clifford regarding the ethics of belief. The conclusion of his argument was that “it is wrong always, everywhere, and for anyone, to believe anything upon insufficient evidence.”

The first thing worth noticing about Clifford’s conclusion is that it is a moral conclusion. Clifford claimed that believing without sufficient evidence is always immoral, irrespective of the identity of the believer or the nature of the belief. That conclusion is undoubtedly too strong. For one thing, belief is not always voluntary. There are many propositions that we believe without evidence that we could not stop believing if we wanted to.

A famous example is the principle of induction, which tells us that we can reliably predict certain aspects of the future based on past experience. All of us rely on this principle instinctively in almost everything we do. For example, we regularly trust other people not to attack us when they see us in public. Why? We (implicitly) reason that because strangers have generally proven friendly or indifferent in the past, they will generally be friendly or indifferent when we encounter them in the future. Based on this reasoning, we leave our guns at home, ignore most of the people we see around us (except attractive members of the opposite sex), and extend our hands in friendship when introduced to someone.

Other examples abound. Reaching for the light switch to turn on the light presumes the principle of induction.

But David Hume famously pointed out that reliance on the principle of induction is an exercise in faith (or an act of question begging for you philosophers). Hume explained that there is no evidence that the future will resemble the past - there is only evidence that past futures resembled past pasts. And if we cite past incidents of the future resembling the past as evidence for our belief that future futures will continue to resemble the past, we are simply assuming (without any evidence whatsoever) that future futures will resemble past futures.

Got that?

Hume’s point was that the only evidence that could possibly justify our belief in the principle of induction is our past experience (the truth of induction is not a logical truth of the “all grandmothers have children” variety). However, relying on past experience to justify any prediction about the future, including our belief that the principle of induction will continue to hold, requires our application of the principle of induction. We have to presume the truth of the principle of induction to cite past experience as a justification for our belief in the principle of induction.

Thus, although there is absolutely no evidence supporting the principle of induction, and there never will be, all of us continue to believe in it. And we could not disbelieve in the principle of induction even if we wanted to (which none of us wants to). There are plenty of other propositions that people cannot make themselves disbelieve or doubt, despite the lack of evidence. This clearly demonstrates that Clifford’s categorical conclusion is too strong.

The second thing worth noticing about Clifford’s conclusion is that “sufficient evidence” is a problematically subjective standard. Clifford’s argument assumes (quite reasonably) that there is a gap between the level of evidence needed to create a belief and the level of evidence needed for the believer to be (morally) justified in believing - otherwise no one could ever believe without justification. But any individual who actually believes something also believes that he possesses sufficient justification for his belief. For Clifford’s conclusion to have moral force, we’d need to know (among many other things) when the evidence is sufficient, objectively speaking, for the particular type of belief in question. And on this topic, severe disagreement is the rule.

It is also clear that a given level of evidence will seem sufficient or insufficient, depending upon the degree to which we want (or don’t want) to believe a given proposition. Clifford would no doubt respond that we have an obligation to attempt to be as objective as possible. But the role desire plays in our perception of the evidence is frequently inscrutable. And because we can hardly be responsible for a feature of our psychology that we can’t even measure, much less fully transcend, the ethical charge that anyone knowingly believed on insufficient evidence will be difficult to sustain.

Clifford’s argument has other problems. I don’t want anyone to think that I think otherwise. However, I find Clifford’s underlying point - that we have a moral obligation to exercise our faculty of belief responsibly - compelling.

I also think many Christians have been systematically trained to ignore this moral obligation, and this constitutes a serious flaw in our culture.

Joe H.

4 comments:

Bilbo Baggins said...

I didn't read Clifford's article but I can't help but note that part of the allure of Christianity or most any faith is the mystery aspect -- that some unexplainable things just are, and then must be accepted.
I was raised in a fundamentalist culture (although baptized into the Episcopal Church as a child by my Aglipayan parents) and found myself drawn from my teenage years onward to more pentacostal groups (in college and law school and right after law school) yet regularly attended Baptist Churches for most of my young adult life. I finally broke down and went to a Hope Chapel, enjoyed the emotionalism and never developed the gift of tongues, but did feel a real presence of something other than myself during worship and in devotion and in everyday life. Although I've returned to a more liturgical church (my spouse was a cradle Episcopalian), I still find that part of what I like about faith is that letting go, that searching for those thin places where we get a glimpse of the divine. . . . So while I understand and appreciate your criticism of Christian reflexive anti-intellectualism, I'm not sure that we don't get to count as "evidence" of our irrational beliefs those moments when we've been touched by God.

Anonymous said...

Hey Bilbo -

Much agreed. I was raised as a very pure agnostic, yet walked around talking to God as a mostly friendless young kid - and knew instinctively that He was there.

In some ways, Seminary was my greatest error - putting God on the table as a subject to be dissected led to the silencing of that voice for nearly 10 years.

Last year's movie "Children of Men" comes to mind. (WARNING - very war-violent movie) The main character finds himself swept up into something that he is very unsure of (rescuing one of the world's last pregnant women) - but if it's true, then God's hand in the world will be revealed.

So he forges onward in uncertainty, risking death countless times, rarely if ever seeing proof of his goal...but striving on in simple hope of its truth.

Why is it that I, a very rational person, would feel so elated if God came through in the end?

It kind of brings up the "Heroes" passage of the book of Hebrews, no?

Joe Huster said...

Bilbo, I think we can count moments of transcendence as evidence. I think we can count various kinds of spirtual experiences as evidence. What concerns me is that we train ourselves to be indifferent to evidence, when it conflicts with what we want to believe.

For example, I suspect that if you went into a randomly selected evangelical church and individually asked the members whether the story of Noah's Ark is litterally true, far more than half of those questioned would answer "yes."

As a factual account of actual events, the Ark story is absurd on its face. And yet, we accept it without much reservation. Just like we accepted Sarah Palin.

That worries me.

Joe H.

Joe Huster said...

Jim,

Thanks for the link to the Sullivan article. I agree with most of what he said. The irony is that "faith" implies a lack of knowledge, but in order to preserve faith were trained to squelch doubt and thereby convince ourselves that we have certainty.

Joe H.